The contested garment (CG) rule,[1] also called concede-and-divide,[2] is a division rule for solving problems of conflicting claims (also called "bankruptcy problems"). The idea is that, if one claimant's claim is less than 100% of the estate to divide, then he effectively concedes the unclaimed estate to the other claimant. Therefore, we first give to each claimant, the amount conceded to him/her by the other claimant. The remaining amount is then divided equally among the two claimants.
The CG rule first appeared in the Mishnah, exemplified by a case of conflict over a garment, hence the name. In the Mishnah, it was described only for two-people problems. But in 1985, Robert Aumann and Michael Maschler have proved that, in every bankruptcy problem, there is a unique division that is consistent with the CG rule for each pair of claimants.[1] They call the rule, that selects this unique division, the CG-consistent rule (it is also called the Talmud rule).[2]
Problem description
There is a divisible resource, denoted by (=Estate or Endowment). There are n people who claim this resource or parts of it; they are called claimants. The amount claimed by each claimant i is denoted by . Usually, , that is, the estate is insufficient to satisfy all the claims. The goal is to allocate to each claimant an amount such that .
Two claimants
With two claimants, the CG rule works in the following way.
- Truncate each claim to the estate (since one is not allowed to claim more than the entire estate). That is, set for each claimant i.
- Allocate to claimant 1 an amount that is, the amount not claimed by 2.
- Allocate to claimant 2 an amount that is, the amount not claimed by 1.
- The remainder is ; divide it equally among the claimants.
Summing the amounts given to each claimant, we can write the following formula:
For example:
- If and , then both claimants get 1/2, that is, .
- If and and . then claimant 1 gets 3/4 and claimant 2 gets 1/4, that is, .
These two examples are first mentioned in the first Mishnah of Bava Metzia:[3]
"Two are holding a garment. One says, "I found it," and the other says, "I found it":
- If one says "all of it is mine" and the other says "all of it is mine", then this one shall swear that he owns no less than half of it, and this one shall swear that he owns no less than half of it, and they shall divide it between them.
- If one says, "all of it is mine" and the other says "half of it is mine", then the one who says "all of it is mine" shall swear that he owns no less than three quarters of it; and the one who says "half of it is mine" shall swear that he owns no less than one quarter of it; the former takes three quarters and the latter takes one quarter."
Many claimants
To extend the CG rule to problems with three or more claimants, we apply the general principle of consistency (also called coherence), which says that every part of a fair division should be fair.[4] In particular, we seek an allocation that respects the CG rule for each pair of claimants. That is, for every claimants i and j:
.
Apriori, it is not clear that such an allocation always exists, or that it is unique. However, it can be proved that a unique CG-consistent allocation always exists.[1] It can be described by the following algorithm:
- If (that is, the total estate is less than half the total claims), then apply the rule of constrained equal awards to half the claims, that is, return .
- Otherwise, : give each claimant half of his/her claim, and then apply the rule of constrained equal losses to the remainder, that is, return .
Note that, with two claimants, once the claims are truncated to be at most the estate, the condition always holds. For example:
- .
Here are some three-claimant examples:
- ; here CEA is used.
- ; here CEA is used.
- ; here either CEA or CEL can be used (the result is the same); when the sum of claims is exactly half the estate, each claimant gets exactly half his/her claim.
- ; here CEL is used.
- ; here CEL is used.
- ; here CEL is used.
The first three examples appear in another Mishnah, in Ketubot:[5]
"Suppose a man, who was married to three women, died; the marriage contract of one wife was for 100 dinars, and the marriage contract of the second wife was for 200 dinars, and the marriage contract of the third wife was for 300, and all three contracts were issued on the same date so that none of the wives has precedence over any of the others.
- If the total value of the estate is only 100 dinars, the wives divide the estate equally.
- If there were 200 dinars in the estate, the first wife takes 50 dinars, while the other two wives take three dinars of gold each, which are the equivalent of 75 silver dinars.
- If there were 300 dinars in the estate, the first wife takes 50 dinars, the second takes 100 dinars, and the third takes six dinars of gold, the equivalent of 150 silver dinars."
Constructive description
The CG rule can be described in a constructive way. Suppose E increases from 0 to the half-sum of the claims: the first units are divided equally, until each claimant receives . Then, the claimant with the smallest is put on hold, and the next units are divided equally among the remaining claimants until each of them up to the next-smallest . Then, the claimant with the second-smallest is put on hold too. This goes on until either the estate is fully divided, or each claimant gets exactly . If some estate remains, then the losses are divided in a symmetric way, starting with an estate equal to the sum of all claims, and decreasing down to half this sum.
Properties
The CG rule is self-dual. This means that it treats gains and losses symmetrically: it divides gains in the same way that it divides losses. Formally: .[1][6]
Game-theoretic analysis
The CG rule can be derived independently, as the nucleolus of a certain cooperative game defined based on the claims.[7]
Piniles' rule
Zvi Menahem Piniles, a 19th-century Jewish scholar, presented a different rule to explain the cases in Ketubot.[8] His rule is similar to the CG rule, but it is not consistent with the CG rule when there are two claimants. The rule works as follows:[2]
- If the sum of claims is larger than 2E, then it applies the CEA rule on half the claims, that is, it returns .
- Otherwise, it gives each agent half its claim and then applies CEA on the remainder, that is, it returns .
Examples with two claimants:
- . Initially the claimants get (30,45). The remaining claims are (30,45) and the remaining estate is 25, so it is divided equally.
- . Initially the claimants get (25,50). The remaining claims are (25,50) and the remaining estate is 25, so it is divided equally.
- . Initially the claimants get (25,50). The remaining claims are (25,50) and the remaining estate is 25, so it is divided equally.
Examples with three claimants:
- . Here the sum of claims is more than twice the estate, so the outcome is .
- . Again the sum of claims is more than twice the estate, so the outcome is .
- . Again the sum of claims is more than twice the estate, so the outcome is .
Further reading
References
- 1 2 3 4 Aumann, Robert J; Maschler, Michael (1985-08-01). "Game theoretic analysis of a bankruptcy problem from the Talmud". Journal of Economic Theory. 36 (2): 195–213. doi:10.1016/0022-0531(85)90102-4. ISSN 0022-0531.
- 1 2 3 William, Thomson (2003-07-01). "Axiomatic and game-theoretic analysis of bankruptcy and taxation problems: a survey". Mathematical Social Sciences. 45 (3): 249–297. doi:10.1016/S0165-4896(02)00070-7. ISSN 0165-4896.
- ↑ Bava Metzia 1:1.
- ↑ Balinski, Michel (2005-06-01). "What Is Just?". The American Mathematical Monthly. 112 (6): 502–511. doi:10.1080/00029890.2005.11920221. ISSN 0002-9890. S2CID 32125041.
- ↑ Ketubot 10:4
- ↑ Dagan, Nir (1996). "New characterizations of old bankruptcy rules". Social Choice and Welfare. 13: 51–59. CiteSeerX 10.1.1.319.3243. doi:10.1007/BF00179098. S2CID 18151768.
- ↑ Robert J. Aumann, Game theory in the Talmud, 2002
- ↑ Piniles, Zvi Menahem (1863). Darkah Shel Torah (Hebrew). Wien: Forester.