Max Weber
Max Weber in 1918, facing right
Portrait by Ernst Gottmann, 1918
Born
Maximilian Karl Emil Weber

(1864-04-21)21 April 1864
Died14 June 1920(1920-06-14) (aged 56)
Alma mater
Notable work
Spouse
(m. 1893)
School
Institutions
Theses
Doctoral advisors
Main interests
  • History
  • economics
  • sociology
  • law
  • religion
Notable ideas
Signature

Maximilian Karl Emil Weber (/ˈvbər/; German: [ˈveːbɐ]; 21 April 1864  14 June 1920) was a German sociologist, historian, jurist and political economist, who is regarded as among the most important theorists of the development of modern Western society. He was one of the central figures in the development of sociology and the social sciences, and his ideas profoundly influence social theory and research.

Born in Erfurt in 1864, Weber studied law and history in Berlin, Göttingen, and Heidelberg. After earning his doctorate in law in 1889 and habilitation in 1891, he married his cousin Marianne Schnitger and taught in Freiburg and Heidelberg. In 1897, he had a breakdown after his father died following an argument. Weber ceased teaching and travelled until the early 1900s. He recovered and wrote The Protestant Ethic and the Spirit of Capitalism. During the First World War, he supported Germany's war effort, but became critical of it and supported democratisation. He also gave the lectures "Science as a Vocation" and "Politics as a Vocation". After the war, Weber cofounded the German Democratic Party, unsuccessfully ran for office, and advised the drafting of the Weimar Constitution. Becoming frustrated with politics, he resumed teaching in Vienna and Munich. He possibly contracted the Spanish flu, and died of pneumonia in 1920 at the age of 56. A book, Economy and Society, was left unfinished.

One of Weber's main intellectual concerns was in understanding the processes of rationalisation, secularisation, and disenchantment. He formulated a thesis arguing that such processes were associated with the rise of capitalism and modernity. Weber also argued that the Protestant ethic caused the creation of capitalism in The Protestant Ethic and the Spirit of Capitalism. It was the earliest part in his broader consideration of the world religions, as he later examined the religions of China, India, and ancient Judaism. In terms of government, Weber argued that states were defined by their monopoly on violence and categorised social authority into three distinct forms: charismatic, traditional, and rational-legal. Weber was also a key proponent of methodological antipositivism, arguing for the study of social action through interpretive rather than purely empiricist methods. Weber made a variety of other contributions to economic sociology, political sociology, and the sociology of religion.

After his death, the rise of Weberian scholarship was slowed by the political instability of the Weimar Republic and the rise of Nazi Germany. In the post-war era, organised scholarship began to appear, led by Talcott Parsons, who used Weber's works to support his idea of structural functionalism. Over the course of the twentieth century, Weber's reputation rose due to the publication of translations of his works and scholarly interpretations of his life and works. He began to be regarded as a founding father of sociology, alongside Karl Marx and Émile Durkheim. As a result of these works, Weber is commonly regarded as one of the central figures in the development of the social sciences.

Biography

Early life and education

Maximilian Karl Emil Weber was born on 21 April 1864 in Erfurt, Province of Saxony, Prussia, but his family moved to Berlin in 1869.[1] He was the oldest of eight children to Max Weber Sr. and his wife Helene Fallenstein.[2] Over the course of his life, Weber Sr. held posts as a lawyer, civil servant, and parliamentarian for the National Liberal Party in the Prussian Landtag and German Reichstag.[3] Fallenstein was partly descended from French Huguenot immigrants and came from a wealthy background.[4] Over time, Weber Jr. would be affected by the marital and personality tensions between his father, "a man who enjoyed earthly pleasures" while overlooking religious and philanthropic causes, and his mother, a devout Calvinist "who sought to lead an ascetic life" and held moral absolutist ideas.[5]

A group photograph of Max Weber with his brothers Alfred and Karl
Max Weber (left) and his brothers, Alfred (center) and Karl (right), in 1879

Weber Sr.'s involvement in public life immersed his home in both politics and academia, as his salon welcomed scholars and public figures such as the philosopher Wilhelm Dilthey, the jurist Levin Goldschmidt, and the historian Theodor Mommsen. The young Max Weber and his brother Alfred, who also became a sociologist, passed their formative years in this intellectual atmosphere.[6] In 1870, Weber entered the Döbbelin private school in Charlottenburg.[7] While in class, bored and unimpressed with his teachers, Weber secretly read all forty volumes by the writer Johann Wolfgang von Goethe.[8] Goethe would later exert an important influence on his thought and methodology.[9] Before entering university, he read many other classical works, including those by the philosopher Immanuel Kant.[10] For Christmas in 1877, a thirteen-year-old Max Weber gifted his parents two historical essays, entitled "About the Course of German history, with Special Reference to the Positions of the Emperor and the Pope", and "About the Roman Imperial Period from Constantine to the Migration Period". Two years later, at roughly the same time of the year, he wrote another historical essay, "Observations on the Ethnic Character, Development, and History of the Indo-European Nations". All of these essays were non-derivative contributions to the philosophy of history and were derived from Weber's reading of "numerous sources".[11]

In 1882, Weber enrolled in Heidelberg University as a law student, later studying at Friedrich Wilhelm University in Berlin and the University of Göttingen.[12] Simultaneously with his studies, he practiced law and worked as a lecturer.[13] In 1886, Weber passed the examination for Referendar, comparable to the bar association examination in the British and U.S. legal systems. Throughout the late 1880s, Weber continued his study of law and history.[14] Under the tutelage of Levin Goldschmidt and Rudolf von Gneist, Weber earned his law doctorate in 1889 by writing a dissertation on legal history titled Development of the Principle of Joint Liability and a Separate Fund of the General Partnership out of the Household Communities and Commercial Associations in Italian Cities. This work would be used as part of a longer work, On the History of Commercial Partnerships in the Middle Ages, Based on Southern European Documents, published in the same year.[15] Two years later, working with the statistician August Meitzen, Weber completed his habilitation, a post-doctoral thesis, titled Roman Agrarian History and Its Significance for Public and Private Law.[16] Having thus become a privatdozent, Weber joined the faculty of Friedrich Wilhelm University, lecturing, doing research, and consulting for the government.[17]

Weber's years as a university student were dotted with several periods of military service, the longest of which lasted between October 1883 to September 1884. During this time, he was in Strasbourg and attended classes taught by his uncle, the historian Hermann Baumgarten.[18] Weber befriended Baumgarten and he influenced Weber's growing liberalism and criticism of Otto von Bismarck's domination of German politics.[19] During his first few years in university, he acted similarly to the other students, who were members of fraternities and placed emphasis on drinking beer and fencing.[20] He was a member of the Burschenschaft Allemannia Heidelberg and obtained several duelling scars on the left side of his face as the result of his duelling.[21] His mother was displeased by his behaviour and slapped him when he came home after his third semester ended in 1883. However, Weber matured, increasingly began to take his mother's side in family arguments, and grew estranged from his father.[22]

Marriage

Max Weber, right, and Marianne, left, in 1894
Max Weber and his wife Marianne in 1894

Max Weber had a relationship and semi-engagement with Emmy Baumgarten, the daughter of Hermann Baumgarten, from 1887 until her declining mental health caused him to break off their relationship five years later.[23] Afterwards, he entered a relationship with his distant cousin Marianne Schnitger in 1893 and married her on 20 September.[24] The marriage granted long-awaited financial independence to Weber, allowing him to finally leave his parents' household.[25] They had no children.[26] Marianne was a feminist activist and an author in her own right.[27] She was instrumental in collecting, editing, and publishing Weber's writings in book form after his death, while her biography of him is an important source for understanding Weber's life.[28] In 1909, they befriended a former student of his, Else von Richthofen, and the pianist Mina Tobler. After a failed attempt to court Richthofen, Weber began an affair with Tobler in 1911.[29] Eight years later, he began a sadomasochistic affair with Richthofen, who was also conducting an affair with his brother, Alfred. These affairs lasted until his death in 1920.[30]

Early work and breakdown

In the years between the completion of his dissertation and habilitation, Weber took an interest in contemporary social policy. In 1888, he joined the Verein für Socialpolitik, a new professional association of German economists affiliated with the historical school. They saw the role of economics primarily as finding solutions to the social problems of the age and pioneered large scale statistical studies of economic issues. He also involved himself in politics, joining the left-leaning Evangelical Social Congress.[31] In 1890, the Verein established a research program to examine "the Polish question", or ostflucht: the influx of Polish farm workers into eastern Germany as local labourers migrated to Germany's rapidly industrialising cities.[32] Weber was put in charge of the study and wrote a large part of the final report, which generated considerable attention and controversy, marking the beginning of Weber's renown as a social scientist.[33]

From 1893 to 1899, Weber was a member of the Pan-German League (Alldeutscher Verband), an organisation that campaigned against the influx of Polish workers; the degree of his support for the Germanisation of Poles and similar nationalist policies continues to be debated by modern scholars.[34] Weber and his wife moved to Freiburg in 1894, where he was appointed professor of economics at the University of Freiburg.[35] During his tenure there, in 1895, he gave a provocative lecture titled "The Nation State and Economic Policy", where he criticised the immigration of Poles and blamed the Junkers for perpetuating Slavic immigration to serve their selfish interests.[36] It influenced the politician Friedrich Naumann to create the National-Social Association, which was a Christian socialist and nationalist political organisation.[37] Weber was pessimistic regarding the association's ability to succeed, and it dissolved after winning a single seat in the Reichstag during the 1903 German federal election.[38] In 1896, Weber accepted an appointment to a chair in economics and finance at Heidelberg University.[39] There, Weber and his wife became the central figures in the eponymous "Weber Circle", which included Georg Jellinek, Ernst Troeltsch, and Werner Sombart. Younger scholars, such as György Lukács and Robert Michels, also joined it.[40]

In 1897, Weber Sr. died two months after a severe quarrel with his son that was never resolved.[41] After this, Weber became increasingly prone to depression, nervousness, and insomnia, which made it difficult for him to fulfill his duties as a professor.[42] His condition forced him seek an exemption from his teaching obligations, which he was granted in 1899. He spent time in the Konstanzer Hof sanatorium in 1898 and a different one near the Swabian Jura in 1900. Weber also travelled to Corsica and Italy between 1899 and 1903 in order to alleviate his illness.[43] He would fully withdraw from teaching in 1903 and did not return to it until 1918.[44] Weber's ordeal with mental illness was carefully described in a personal chronology that was later destroyed by his widow. The reason for its destruction was possibly because Marianne feared that Weber's work would be discredited by the Nazis if his experience with mental illness were widely known.[45]

Later work

Max Weber in 1907, holding a hookah
Max Weber in 1907

Once he had recovered from his illness, he accepted a position as an associate editor of the Archiv für Sozialwissenschaft und Sozialpolitik in 1904, alongside his colleagues Edgar Jaffé and Werner Sombart. It facilitated his reintroduction to academia and became one of the most prominent social science journals as a result of his efforts.[46] Weber published some of his most seminal papers in this journal, notably his book The Protestant Ethic and the Spirit of Capitalism, which became his most famous work and laid the foundations for his later research on the impact of religion on the development of economic systems.[47] In it, he argued that the source for the "spirit of capitalism" was in the Reformation. More specifically, he traced it to the Puritan religions. They placed great importance on work, to a degree where other actions mattered less.[48] They had a religious calling to work that caused them to systematically obtain wealth. The Puritans wished to prove that they were members of the elect who were destined to go to Heaven.[49] Benjamin Franklin's personal ethic, as described in his "Advice to a Young Tradesman", was used as an example of the economic ethic that the Protestant sects had.[50] The thesis also contained themes that Weber would later prove central to his scholarship: rationalisation and the ideal type.[51] Rationalisation pertained to the increasing systemisation of life that ultimately caused religious influence to decline.[52] Rationalisation also caused Western society to be caught in the "stahlhartes Gehäuse" ("iron cage" or "steel-hard casing") that was the economic order that was created by modern capitalism.[53] The ideal types were representative figures, or case studies, that represented concepts.[54]

Also in 1904, Max Weber was invited to participate in the Congress of Arts and Sciences held in connection with the World's fair (Louisiana Purchase Exposition) in St. Louis, alongside his wife, Werner Sombart, Ernst Troeltsch, and other German scholars.[55] Taking advantage of the fair, the Webers embarked on a trip that began and ended in New York City and lasted for almost three months. They travelled throughout the country, from New England to the Deep South. Different communities were visited, including German immigrant towns and African American communities.[56] Among the places visited was North Carolina, where some of his relatives in the Fallenstein family had settled.[57] Weber used the trip to learn more about America and this experience played a role in the development of the Protestant work ethic. He used the trip to find social and theological conditions that could contribute to his thesis. Weber also used the trip to further his knowledge of the United States' social and economic conditions more generally.[58] After returning, Weber felt that he was unable to resume regular teaching at that time and continued on as a private scholar, helped by an inheritance in 1907.[59] In 1909, disappointed with the Verein, he co-founded the German Sociological Association (Deutsche Gesellschaft für Soziologie) and served as its first treasurer. He resigned from the position in 1912.[60]

Political involvements

Later, during the spring of 1913, Weber holidayed in the Monte Verità community in Ascona.[61] While holidaying, he was advising Frieda Gross in her custody battle for her children. He opposed Erich Mühsam's involvement due to Mühsam's support for anarchism, arguing that the case needed to be dealt with by bourgeois reformers who were not "derailed".[62] A year later, also in spring, he again holidayed in Ascona.[63] In the community, there were several different expressions of the radical political and lifestyle reform movements that were in existence at the time. They included naturism, free love, and Western esotericism, among others. Weber was critical of the anarchist and erotic movements in Ascona, as he viewed their fusion as having been politically absurd.[64]

First World War

At the outbreak of First World War, Weber, aged 50, volunteered for service and was appointed as a reserve officer in charge of organising the army hospitals in Heidelberg, a role he fulfilled until the end of 1915.[65] Weber's views on the war and the expansion of the German Empire changed during the course of the conflict.[66] Early on, he supported nationalist rhetoric and the war effort, though with some hesitation, viewing the war as a necessity to fulfill German duty as a leading state power. In time, however, Weber became one of the most prominent critics of both German expansionism and the Kaiser's war policies.[67] Weber publicly criticised the Belgian annexation policy and unrestricted submarine warfare, later supporting calls for constitutional reform, democratisation, and universal suffrage.[68]

Max Weber, facing right, lecturing with Ernst Toller in the center of the background
Max Weber (facing right) with Ernst Toller (facing camera) during the Lauenstein Conferences in 1917

He and his wife also participated in the 1917 Lauenstein Conferences that were held at Lauenstein Castle in Bavaria.[69] These conferences were planned by the publisher Eugen Diederichs for the purpose of bringing together intellectuals who would create a new age for Germany. Theodor Heuss, Ernst Toller, and Werner Sombart were among the other intellectuals who were invited.[70] Weber's presence elevated his profile in Germany and served to dispel some of the romantic atmosphere of the event. After he spoke at the first one, he became involved in the planning for the second one, as Diederichs thought that the conferences needed someone who could serve as an oppositional figure. In this capacity, he argued against the political romanticism that was being espoused by Max Maurenbrecher, a former theologian. Weber also opposed what he saw as the excessive rhetoric of the youth groups and nationalists at Lauenstein, instead supporting the democratisation of Germany.[71] For Weber and the younger participants, the romantic intent of the conferences was irrelevant to the determination of Germany's future.[72]

In November, shortly after the second conference, Weber was invited by the Free Student Youth, a student organisation, to give a lecture in Munich. The resulting lecture was titled "Science as a Vocation".[73] In it, he described an inner calling as having been necessary for one to enter scholarship. The potential for a lack of success and career advancement was also an aspect of the career path. Weber thought that only a particular type of person would be able to make a career in academia. He used his own career as an example of a person whose career was in academia. Recalling the arguments that he made regarding the Protestant ethic, he stated that the path forward in scholarship required the scholar to be self-denying and methodical in their research. The modern scholar was to be a specialist who would be able to avoid amateurism.[74] A major aspect of his commentary on the role of the scholar in modernity related to disenchantment and intellectual rationalisation. These processes resulted in the nature of life itself being questioned, creating the further question of the role of scholarship in life. Weber argued that scholarship could provide certainty through the use of its starting presumptions, in spite of its inability to give absolute answers.[75]

Weimar Republic

Following the end of the war, Weber unsuccessfully ran for a seat in the Weimar National Assembly in January 1919 as a member of the liberal German Democratic Party, which he had co-founded.[76] He also advised the National Assembly in its drafting of the Weimar Constitution.[77] While he was campaigning for his party, Weber critiqued the left and complained about the leaders of the leftist Spartacus League, Karl Liebknecht and Rosa Luxemburg, that controlled the city government of Berlin at the time. He regarded the German Revolution of 1918–1919 as having been responsible for Germany's inability to fight against Poland's claims on its territory in the east.[78] His opposition to it may have prevented Friedrich Ebert, the new president of Germany and a member of the Social Democratic Party, from appointing Weber as a minister or ambassador.[79] Weber was, at the same time, critical of the Treaty of Versailles, which he believed unjustly assigned war guilt to Germany. Instead, Weber believed that many countries were guilty of starting it, not just Germany.[80] In making this case, Weber argued that Russia was the only great power that actually desired the war. He also regarded Germany as not having been culpable for the invasion of Belgium.[81] Overall, Weber's political efforts were largely unsuccessful, with the exception of his support for a strong presidency that would be democratically elected.[82]

Max Weber in 1918, facing right and looking at the camera
Max Weber in 1918

On 28 January 1919, after his electoral defeat, Weber delivered a lecture titled "Politics as a Vocation", which commented on what he saw as the inherent violence and dishonesty among politicians.[83] About the nature of politicians, he concluded that, "in nine out of ten cases they are windbags puffed up with hot air about themselves. They are not in touch with reality, and they do not feel the burden they need to shoulder; they just intoxicate themselves with romantic sensations."[84] His lecture was prompted by the political turmoil of the early Weimar Republic and was requested by the Free Student Youth. He defined politics as having been divided into three aspects: passion, judgment, and responsibility. There was also a division between conviction and responsibility. These two concepts were sharply divided, but it was possible for them to be present in a single individual, particularly the ideal politician.[85] The types of authority were themselves divided into traditional, charismatic, and rational-legal.[86] Ultimately, Weber thought that the resolution to the political issues of his day required consistent effort, rather than the quick solutions that the students preferred.[87]

Shortly before he left to join the delegation in Versailles on 13 May 1919, Max Weber used his connections with the deputies of the German National People's Party to meet with Erich Ludendorff. He spent several hours unsuccessfully trying to convince Ludendorff to surrender himself to the Allies.[88] This debate also shifted to other subjects, such as who was culpable for the failure of the war effort. Weber thought that the high command had failed, while Ludendorff regarded Weber as a supporter of democracy who was partially responsible for the revolution. Weber tried to disabuse him of that notion by arguing in favour of a democracy that would have a strong executive power. Since he held Ludendorff responsible for the failure of the German war effort and having sent many young Germans to die on the battlefield, Weber thought that he should surrender himself and assume the status of a political martyr. However, Ludendorff was not willing to do so and wished to simply live off of his pension.[89]

Last years

A photograph of Max Weber's grave
Weber's grave in Heidelberg

Frustrated with politics, Weber resumed teaching, first at the University of Vienna in 1918, then at the Ludwig Maximilian University of Munich in 1919.[90] Some of his lectures from that period were later collected into the General Economic History, which was published in 1923.[91] In Vienna, Weber filled a previously vacant chair in political economy that he had been in consideration for since October 1917.[92] Later, in Munich, he was appointed to Lujo Brentano's chair in social science, economic history, and political economy. He accepted the appointment in order to be closer to his mistress, Else von Richthofen.[93] Many colleagues and students in Munich attacked his response to the German Revolution, while some right-wing students held protests in front of his home.[94]

In early 1920, Max Weber gave a seminar that contained a discussion of Oswald Spengler's The Decline of the West.[95] Weber respected him and privately described him as having been "a very brilliant and scholarly dilettante".[96] That seminar provoked some of his students, who knew Spengler personally, to suggest that he debate Spengler alongside other scholars. They met in the Munich town hall and debated for two days.[97] The audience was primarily young Germans of different political perspectives, including communists. While neither Weber nor Spengler were able to convince the other of their points, Weber was more cautious and careful in his arguments against Spengler than the other debaters were. After the debate, the students did not feel that they had an answer to the question of what should be done to resolve the issues that Germany faced after the end of the First World War.[96]

Lili, one of Max Weber's sisters, committed suicide on 7 April 1920 as a result of the end of her affair with the pedagogue Paul Geheeb.[98] Weber and his wife took in their four children and planned to raise them. He was uncomfortable with his newfound role as a father figure, but thought that Marianne had been fulfilled as a woman by this event. She later formally adopted the children in 1928. Weber wished for her to stay with the children in Heidelberg or move closer to Geheeb's Odenwaldschule ("Odenwald School"), so that he could be alone in Munich with his mistress, Else von Richthofen. He left the decision to Marianne, who said that only he could make the decision to leave for himself.[99]

On 4 June 1920, Weber's students were informed that he needed to cancel classes due to a cold. By 14 June 1920, the cold had turned into influenza and he died of pneumonia in Munich.[100] He had likely contracted the Spanish flu and been subjected to insufficient medical care. Else von Richthofen, who was present for his death alongside his wife, thought that he could have survived his illness if he had been given better treatment.[101] His body was cremated and the ashes were buried in Heidelberg.[102] At the time of his death, Weber had not finished writing his magnum opus on sociological theory: Economy and Society. His widow, Marianne, helped prepare it for its publication in 1922.[103]

Methodology

Sociology, for Max Weber, was "a science which attempts the interpretive understanding of social action in order thereby to arrive at a causal explanation of its course and effects".[104] Made clear in his methodology, Weber distinguished himself from Durkheim, Marx, and other classical figures, in that his primary focus was on individuals and culture.[105] Whereas Durkheim focused on the society, Weber concentrated on the individual and their actions (i.e. structure and action). Compared to Marx, who argued for the primacy of the material world over the world of ideas, Weber valued ideas as motivating actions of individuals.[106] He was open to the idea that social phenomena could have several different causes, which separated him from Marx's determinism.[105]

Verstehen

In terms of methodology, Weber was primarily concerned with the question of objectivity and subjectivity, going on to distinguish social action from social behavior, noting that social action must be understood through how individuals subjectively relate to one another.[107] According to him, the study of social action through interpretive means or verstehen ("to understand") needed to be based upon understanding the subjective meaning and purpose that individuals attached to their actions.[108] Social actions may have had easily identifiable and objective means, but might have had much more subjective ends.[109] Weber noted that the importance of subjectivity in the social sciences made the creation of fool-proof, universal laws much more difficult than in the natural sciences and that the amount of objective knowledge that social sciences were able to create was limited. Overall, Weber supported the goal of objective science as one worth striving for, though he noted that it was ultimately an unreachable goal.[110]

There is no absolutely "objective" scientific analysis of culture. … All knowledge of cultural reality … is always knowledge from particular points of view. … An "objective" analysis of cultural events, which proceeds according to the thesis that the ideal of science is the reduction of empirical reality to "laws", is meaningless [because] the knowledge of social laws is not knowledge of social reality but is rather one of the various aids used by our minds for attaining this end.

—Max Weber in Sociological Writings, 1904.[111]

The principle of methodological individualism, which holds that social scientists should seek to understand collectivities solely as the result and the context of the actions of individual persons, can be traced to Weber, particularly to the first chapter of Economy and Society, in which he argued that only individuals "can be treated as agents in a course of subjectively understandable action".[112] In other words, Weber contended that social phenomena can be understood scientifically only to the extent that they are captured by models of the behaviour of purposeful individuals  models that Weber called "ideal types"  from which actual historical events necessarily deviate due to accidental and irrational factors.[113] The analytical constructs of an ideal type never exist in reality, but provide objective benchmarks against which real-life constructs can be measured.[114]

Weber's methodology was developed in the context of wider debates about methodology of social sciences.[115] The first of which was the Methodenstreit ("method dispute").[116] His position was close to historicism, as he understood social actions as being heavily tied to particular historical contexts and its analysis required the understanding of subjective motivations of individuals.[117] Therefore, his methodology emphasised the use of comparative historical analysis.[118] As such, he was more interested in explaining how a certain outcome was the result of various historical processes rather than predicting an outcome of those processes in the future.[119] The second debate that shaped Weber's perspective on methodology was the Werturteilsstreit ("value-judgment dispute").[120] This debate was held between 1909 and 1914 on the subject of value-judgements in the social sciences. It originated with a debate between the supporters of the idea that ethics was an important consideration in the field of economics and those who opposed that in the Verein für Socialpolitik.[121] Weber's position was that the social sciences should strive to be value-free. In his view, scholars and students needed to avoid using their position to promote political values in the classroom. The choosing of values was something that science had no part in. With regards to economics, he argued that the productivity was not a useful scientific concept, as it could impede the proper evaluation of economic phenomena.[122]

Theories

Rationalisation

rationalisation and the question of individual freedom in an increasingly rational society, was a central theme in Weber's scholarship.[123] This theme was situated in the larger context of the relationship between psychological motivations, cultural values, and beliefs, and the structure of the society.[119] Weber understood rationalisation as the individual cost-benefit calculation, the wider bureaucratic organisation of the organisations, and the opposite of understanding the reality through mystery and magic.[124] Weber's studies of the subject began with The Protestant Ethic and the Spirit of Capitalism.[51] In it, he argued that the redefinition of the connection between work and piety in Protestantism and especially in ascetic Protestant denominations, particularly Calvinism, shifted human effort towards rational efforts aimed at achieving economic gain.[125] In Protestantism, piety towards God was expressed through one's secular vocation.[126] The rational roots of this doctrine, he argued, soon grew incompatible with and larger than the religious and so the latter were eventually discarded.[127]

What Weber depicted was not only the secularisation of Western culture, but also and especially the development of modern societies from the viewpoint of rationalisation. The new structures of society were marked by the differentiation of the two functionally intermeshing systems that had taken shape around the organisational cores of the capitalist enterprise and the bureaucratic state apparatus. Weber understood this process as the institutionalisation of purposive-rational economic and administrative action. To the degree that everyday life was affected by this cultural and societal rationalisation, traditional forms of life  which in the early modern period were differentiated primarily according to one's trade  were dissolved.

Jürgen Habermas in The Philosophical Discourse of Modernity: Twelve Lectures, 1990.[128]

Weber continued his investigation into this matter in later works, notably in his studies on bureaucracy and on the classification of legitimate authority into three types  rational-legal, traditional, and charismatic  of which rational-legal was the dominant one in the modern world.[129] In these works, Weber described what he saw as society's movement towards rationalisation.[130] Rationalisation could also be seen in the economy, with the development of highly rational and calculating capitalism.[131] State bureaucracy and capitalism served as the twin pillars of the developing rational society. The preexisting traditions that relied on the trades were eliminated as a result of those changes.[128] Weber also saw rationalisation as one of the main factors setting the European West apart from the rest of the world.[132]

Features of rationalisation included increasing knowledge, growing impersonality and enhanced control of social and material life.[133] Weber was ambivalent towards rationalisation. He admitted that it was responsible for many advances, particularly freeing humans from traditional, restrictive, and illogical social guidelines. However, he also criticised it for dehumanising individuals as "cogs in the machine" and curtailing their freedom, trapping them in the bureaucratic "iron cage" of rationality and bureaucracy.[134] Related to rationalisation was the process of disenchantment, in which the world was becoming more explained and less mystical, moving from polytheistic religions to monotheistic ones and finally to the Godless science of modernity.[135] However, another interpretation of Weber's theory of disenchantment, advanced by the philosopher Jason Josephson Storm, claimed that Weber did not envision a binary between rationalisation and magical thinking, and that Weber actually referred to the sequestering and professionalisation of magic when he described disenchantment, not to the disappearances of magic.[136] Regardless, for Weber the processes of rationalisation affected all of society, removing "sublime values … from public life" and making art less creative.[137]

The Rational and Social Foundations of Music

Max Weber also applied rationalisation to music in his The Rational and Social Foundations of Music.[138] In writing it, he was partially influenced by his affair with the pianist Mina Tobler. Meanwhile, the scholarly impetus was a sense that Western music was the only type that had become harmonic, while the music of other cultures was more intense and focused on hearing.[139] He thought that music was becoming increasingly rational and had moved away from the conditions that had defined it under feudalism. Similarly, he argued that changes in the construction of musical instruments and simultaneous social and economic changes had influenced that shift. Musical instruments became more advanced as new materials and construction processes were developed, while the socio-economic positions of the players of different instruments shifted.[140] In creating this theory, he was influenced by the scientist Hermann von Helmholtz's application of science to the discussion of harmonisation in music. Weber opposed his interpretation of it, which he viewed as having been reductionist.[141]

Sociology of religion

Weber's work in the field of sociology of religion began with the book The Protestant Ethic and the Spirit of Capitalism.[47] It continued with his analyses in The Religion of China, The Religion of India, and Ancient Judaism.[142] His work on other religions, however, would be interrupted by his sudden death in 1920, which prevented him from following Ancient Judaism with studies of early Christianity and Islam.[143] The three main themes within the books were: religious ideas' effect on economic activities, the relationship between social stratification and religious ideas, and the distinguishable characteristics of Western civilisation.[144] His goal was to find reasons for the different developmental paths of the cultures of the Western world and the Eastern world, without making value judgments, unlike the contemporaneous social Darwinists. Weber simply wanted to explain the distinctive elements of Western civilisation.[145] Weber also proposed a socio-evolutionary model of religious change where societies moved from magic to ethical monotheism, with the intermediatory steps of polytheism, pantheism, and monotheism. According to him, this was the result of growing economic stability, which allowed for professionalisation and the evolution of an increasingly sophisticated priesthood.[146] As societies grew more complex and encompassed different groups, a hierarchy of gods developed. Meanwhile, as their power became more centralised, the concept of a universal God became more popular and desirable.[147]

The Protestant Ethic and the Spirit of Capitalism

The development of the concept of the calling quickly gave to the modern entrepreneur a fabulously clear conscience  and also industrious workers; he gave to his employees as the wages of their ascetic devotion to the calling and of co-operation in his ruthless exploitation of them through capitalism the prospect of eternal salvation.

—Max Weber in The Protestant Ethic and the Spirit of Capitalism, 1905.[126]

The Protestant Ethic and the Spirit of Capitalism is Weber's most famous work.[148] It was the start of his research on how religions affected how economic systems developed.[47] In the book, Weber put forward the thesis that the Protestant ethic, which was derived from the theological ideas of the Reformation, influenced the development of capitalism.[149] Weber was looking for electoral affinities between the Protestant ethic and capitalism.[150] He noted that there was at post-Reformation shift of Europe's economic centre away from Catholic countries such as France, Spain and Italy, and towards Protestant countries such as the Netherlands, England, Scotland, and Germany. Weber also noted that societies that had more Protestants also had a more highly developed capitalist economy.[151] Similarly, in societies with different religions, most successful business leaders were Protestant.[152] Weber thus argued that Roman Catholicism impeded the development of the capitalist economy in the West, as did other religions such as Confucianism and Buddhism elsewhere in the world.[126]

Christian religious devotion had historically been accompanied by rejection of mundane affairs, including economic pursuit.[153] Weber showed that certain types of Protestantism  notably Calvinism  were supportive of rational pursuit of economic gain and worldly activities dedicated to it, seeing them as endowed with moral and spiritual significance.[154] Weber argued that the origin of modern capitalism was in the religious ideas of the Reformation.[155] The "spirit of capitalism" was found in the desire to work hard in a way that pleased the worker and signified their worth, originally had a basis in theology.[156] In particular, the Protestant ethic motivated the believers to work hard, be successful in business, and reinvest their profits in further development rather than frivolous pleasures.[157] Weber thought that self-restraint, hard work, and a belief that wealth could be a sign of salvation were representative of "ascetic Protestantism".[158] The notion of a calling, when combined with Predestination, meant that each individual had to take action to prove their salvation to themselves.[159] However, the success that the religious principles created ultimately removed them as an influence on modern capitalism as a result of its creation of a worldly perspective. As a result, the inheritors of that system were entrapped in a socioeconomic "iron cage".[53]

The Religion of China

The Religion of China: Confucianism and Taoism was Weber's second major work on the sociology of religion. Hans Gerth edited and translated this text into English.[160] Weber focused on those aspects of Chinese society that were different from those of Western Europe, especially those aspects that contrasted with Puritanism. As part of that, he questioned why capitalism had not developed in China.[161] He focused on the issues of Chinese urban development, Chinese patrimonialism and officialdom and Chinese religion and philosophy (primarily Confucianism and Taoism), as the areas in which Chinese development significantly differed from the European route.[162] According to Weber, Confucianism and Puritanism were superficially similar, but were actually largely different from one another.[163] Instead, they were mutually exclusive types of rational thought, each attempting to prescribe a way of life based on religious dogma.[164] Notably, they both valued self-control and restraint and did not oppose accumulation of wealth. However, both of those qualities were simply means to different final goals.[165] Confucianism's goal was "a cultured status position", while Puritanism's goal was to create individuals who were "tools of God". For Weber, Puritans sought rational control of the world and rejected its irrationality while Confucians sought rational acceptance of that state of affairs.[166] Therefore, Weber stated that it was the difference in social attitudes and mentality, shaped by the respective dominant religions, that contributed to the development of capitalism in the West and the absence of it in China.[167]

The Religion of India

The Religion of India: The Sociology of Hinduism and Buddhism was Weber's third major work on the sociology of religion. In this work he dealt with the structure of Indian society, with the orthodox doctrines of Hinduism and the heterodox doctrines of Buddhism, with modifications brought by the influence of popular religiosity and finally with the impact of religious beliefs on the secular ethic of Indian society.[168] In Weber's view, Hinduism in India, like Confucianism in China, was a barrier for capitalism.[169] The Indian caste system, which developed in post-Classical India and served as the source for legitimate social interactions, served as a key part of that. Both Hinduism and the high status of the Brahmins upheld the caste system. The Brahmins used their monopoly on education and theological authority to maintain their position, while Hinduism created a psychological justification for it in the form of the cycle of reincarnation.[170] A person's position in the caste order was thought to have been determined by one's actions in their past life.[171] As a result, advancement of the soul and obeying the predetermined order were more important than seeking advancement in the material world, including economic advancement.[172]

Weber ended his research of society and religion in India by bringing in insights from his previous work on China to discuss similarities of the Asian belief systems.[173] He noted that the believers saw the meaning of life as otherworldly mystical experience.[174] The social world was fundamentally divided between the educated elite, following the guidance of a prophet or wise man and the uneducated masses whose beliefs are centered on magic. In Asia, there was no Messianic prophecy to give both educated and uneducated followers meaning in their regular lives.[175] Weber juxtaposed such Messianic prophecies, notably from the Near East, with the exemplary prophecies found on the Asian mainland, focused more on reaching to the educated elites and enlightening them on the proper ways to live one's life, usually with little emphasis on hard work and the material world.[176] It was those differences that prevented the countries of the Occident from following the paths of the earlier Chinese and Indian civilisations. His next work, Ancient Judaism, was an attempt to prove this theory.[177]

Ancient Judaism

In Ancient Judaism, his fourth major work on the sociology of religion, Weber attempted to explain the factors that resulted in the early differences between Eastern and Western religiosity.[178] He contrasted the innerworldly asceticism developed by Western Christianity with mystical contemplation of the kind developed in India.[179] Weber noted that some aspects of Christianity sought to conquer and change the world, rather than withdraw from its imperfections.[178] This fundamental characteristic of Christianity originally stemmed from ancient Jewish prophecy.[180] Weber classified Jewish people as having been a "pariah people", which meant that they were separated from the society that contained them.[181] He examined the creation and social structure of the ancient Jewish people. In his view, the Israelites maintained order through a covenant with the war god Yahweh and the practice of warrior asceticism. Under Solomon, that changed into a more law-based and organised society than the old confederation was. Religiously, the priests replaced the previous charismatic religious leaders. Weber interpreted the rise of prophets from the shepherds as having begun with Elijah, who promulgated political prophesies and served as an opponent of the monarchy.[182]

Theodicy

The concept of theodicy played a role in Max Weber's interpretation of theology and religion throughout his corpus. This involved both his scholarly and personal interests in the subject. Theodicy was central to Weber's conception of humanity, which he interpreted as having been connected with finding meaning. Theodicy was a popular subject of study amongst German scholars who sought to determine how a world created by an omnibenevolent and omnipotent being can contain suffering. As part of this tradition, Weber was careful in his study of the subject.[183] Rather than interpreting it through a theological or ethical lens, Weber interpreted it through a social one.[184] Furthermore, he incorporated Friedrich Nietzsche's concept of Ressentiment into his discussion of the topic. However, he disagreed with Nietzsche's emotional discussion of the topic and his interpretation of it as having been a Jewish-derived expression of slave morality.[185]

He divided theodicy into three main types:[186]

  1. Persian dualism – God is not all powerful and misfortune comes from outside his power
  2. Indian doctrine of karma – God is not all powerful and misfortune comes from inside oneself
  3. Doctrine of predestination – Only a chosen few will be saved from damnation

Weber defined the importance of societal class within religion by examining the difference between the theodicies of fortune and misfortune and to what class structures they apply.[187] The concept of the work ethic was attached to the theodicy of fortune. Therefore, because of the Protestant work ethic, there was an increase of higher class outcomes and more education among Protestants.[188] Those without the work ethic believed in the theodicy of misfortune, believing wealth and happiness were granted in the afterlife. Another example of how this belief of religious theodicy influences class, was that those of lower economic status the poor, tended towards deep religiousness and faith as a way to comfort themselves and provided hope for a more prosperous future, while those of higher economic status preferred the sacraments or actions that proved their right to possess greater wealth.[189]

The state, politics, and government

In political sociology, one of Weber's most influential contributions is his lecture "Politics as a Vocation", in which he defined "the state" as an entity that was "based on the legitimate use of force".[190] Accordingly, Weber proposed that politics is the sharing of state power between various groups, whereas political leaders were those who wield this power.[191] A politician needed to marry the oppositional gesinnungsethik and verantwortungsethik (the "ethic of conviction" and the "ethic of responsibility").[192] An adherent of the verantwortungsethik would justify their actions based on their consequences. Meanwhile, an adherent of the gesinnungsethik would justify their actions based on their ideals. While Weber thought that they would ideally be present in a politician, he associated them with different types of people and mindsets. These different types of people and mindsets reflected the pacifists and those who wanted to undo Germany's loss in the First World War, respectively.[193]

Weber distinguished three ideal types of legitimate authority:[194]

  1. Charismatic authorityfamilial and religious
  2. Traditional authoritypatriarchs, patrimonialism, feudalism
  3. Rational-legal authority – modern law and state, bureaucracy

In his view, every historical relation between rulers and ruled contained such elements, which could be analysed on the basis of this tripartite distinction.[195] Weber noted that the instability of charismatic authority forces it to routinise into a more structured form of authority.[196] In an ideal type of traditional rule, sufficient resistance to a ruler would lead to a "traditional revolution". The move towards a rational-legal structure of authority, using a bureaucratic structure, is inevitable in the end.[197] Therefore, this theory could sometimes be viewed as part of the sociocultural evolution theory. That was tied to his broader concept of rationalisation by suggesting the inevitability of a move in this direction.[198]

Weber described many ideal types of public administration and government in his Economy and Society. His critical study of the bureaucratisation of society became one of the most enduring parts of his work.[199] Weber began the study of bureaucracy and his works led to the popularisation of the term.[200] Many aspects of contemporary public administration date back to him and a classic, hierarchically organised civil service of the Continental type is called "Weberian civil service".[201] As the most efficient and rational way of organising, bureaucratisation for Weber was the key part of the rational-legal authority. Furthermore, he saw it as the key process in the ongoing rationalisation of the Western society.[199]

Weber listed several preconditions for the emergence of the bureaucracy, which resulted in a need for a more efficient administrative system, including:[202]

  1. The growth in space and population being administered
  2. The growth in complexity of the administrative tasks being carried out and the existence of a monetary economy

The development of communication and transportation technologies made more efficient administration possible, and popularly requested, and the democratisation and rationalisation of culture resulted in demands that the new system treat everyone equally.[202] Weber's ideal bureaucracy was characterised by hierarchical organisation, delineated lines of authority in a fixed area of activity, action taken on the basis of written rules, bureaucratic officials needing expert training, rules being implemented neutrally, and career advancement depending on technical qualifications judged by organisations.[203] While recognising bureaucracy as the most efficient form of organisation and even indispensable for the modern state, Weber also saw it as a threat to individual freedoms and the ongoing bureaucratisation as leading to a "polar night of icy darkness", in which increasing rationalisation of human life traps individuals in the aforementioned "iron cage" of bureaucratic, rule-based, rational control.[204] To counteract bureaucrats, the system needed entrepreneurs and politicians.[205]

Social stratification

Weber also formulated a three-component theory of stratification, with social class, social status and political party as conceptually distinct elements.[206] The three-component theory of stratification contrasted with Karl Marx simpler theory of social class that ties all social stratification to what people own. In Weber's theory, issues of honour and prestige were important. This distinction was most clearly described in Weber's essay "The Distribution of Power Within the Gemeinschaft: Classes, Stände, Parties", which was first published in his book Economy and Society.[207]

The three components of Weber's theory are:[207]

  1. Social class – Based on an economically determined relationship with the market
  2. Status (Stand) – Based on non-economic qualities such as honour and prestige
  3. Party – Affiliations in the political domain

Weber scholars maintain a sharp distinction between the terms "status" and "class", although non-scholars tend to use them interchangeably in casual use. Status and its focus on honour emerged from the Gemeinschaft, which denoted the part of society where loyalty originated from. Class emerged from the Gesellschaft, a subdivision of the Gemeinschaft that included rationally driven markets and legal organisation. Party emerged from a combination of the two.[208] Weber interpreted "life chances", the opportunities to improve one's life, as having been a definitional aspect of class. It related to the differences in access to opportunities that different people might have had in their lives.[209]

Study of the city

The origin of a rational and inner-worldly ethic is associated in the Occident with the appearance of thinkers and prophets … who developed in a social context that was alien to the Asiatic cultures. This context consisted of the political problems engendered by the bourgeois status-group of the city, without which neither Judaism, nor Christianity, nor the development of Hellenistic thinking are conceivable.

—Max Weber in The City, 1921.[210]

As part of his overarching effort to understand the unique development of the Western world, Weber produced a detailed general study of the city as the characteristic locus of the social and economic relations, political arrangements, and ideas that eventually came to define the West. This resulted in a monograph, The City.[211] According to Weber, the city as a politically autonomous organisation of people living in close proximity, employed in a variety of specialised trades, and physically separated from the surrounding countryside. That structure only fully developed in the West and significantly shaped its cultural evolution.[212] Weber argued that Judaism, early Christianity, theology, and later the political party and modern science, were only possible in the urban context that reached a full development in the West alone.[213] He also saw in the history of medieval European cities the rise of a unique form of "non-legitimate domination" that successfully challenged the existing forms of legitimate domination (traditional, charismatic, and rational-legal) that had prevailed until then in the Medieval world.[214]

Economics

Weber regarded himself primarily as an economist, and all his professorial appointments were in economics, though today his contributions in that field are largely overshadowed by his role as a founder of modern sociology.[215] As a political economist and economic historian, Weber belonged to the German historical school of economics, represented by academics such as Gustav von Schmoller and his student Werner Sombart.[216] However, even though Weber's research interests were very much in line with this school, his views on methodology and marginal utility diverged significantly from those of other German historicists. Instead, they were closer to those of Carl Menger and the Austrian school, the traditional rivals of the historical school.[217] The division caused by the Methodenstreit caused Weber to support a broad interpretation of economics that combined economic theory, economic history, and economic sociology in the form of Sozialökonomik ("social economics").[218]

Economy and Society

A page from the Economy and Society manuscript
A page from the manuscript of the sociology of law within Economy and Society

Weber's magnum opus Economy and Society is an essay collection that he was working on at the time of his death in 1920. After his death, the final organisation and editing of the book fell to his widow Marianne. The final German form published in 1922 reflected Marianne's editorial work and intellectual commitment.[219] The composition includes a wide range of essays dealing with Weber's views regarding sociology, social philosophy, politics, social stratification, world religion, diplomacy, and other subjects.[220] Beginning in 1956, the German jurist Johannes Winckelmann began editing and organising the German edition of Economy and Society based on his study of the papers that Weber left at his death. English versions of the work were published as a collected volume in 1968, as edited by Guenther Roth and Claus Wittich. As a result of the various editions in German and English, there are differences between the organisation of the different volumes.[221]

Methodological individualism

While his research interests placed a strong emphasis on interpreting economic history, Weber's support of methodological individualism represented a break with the historical school and an agreement with the founder of the Austrian school of economics, Carl Menger, in the Methodenstreit ("debate over methods").[222] The phrase "methodological individualism", which came into common usage in modern debates regarding the connection between microeconomics and macroeconomics, was coined by the Austrian-American economist Joseph Schumpeter in 1908 as a way of referring to the views of Weber.[113] Despite the usage of "individualism" in the term, Weber did not interpret the individual as being the true source for sociological explanations. Instead, while only individuals could engage in intentional action, they were not necessarily separate from the collective group.[223] He interpreted methodological individualism as having had close proximity to verstehende ("interpretive") sociology, as actions can be interpreted subjectively. Similarly, it is also related to ideal types in that it involves discussions of abstract and rational models of human behaviour.[224]

Marginal utility

Unlike other historicists, Weber accepted Marginal utility and taught it to his students.[225] Weber's overall economic sociology was based on it.[226] In 1908, Weber published an article, "Marginal Utility Theory and 'The Fundamental Law of Psychophysics'", in which he drew a sharp methodological distinction between psychology and economics and attacked the claims that the marginal theory of value in economics reflected the form of the psychological response to stimuli as described by the Weber–Fechner law. This article was also a rejection of the dependence of the economic theory of value on the laws of psychophysics.[227] Weber also included a similar discussion of marginal utility theory in the second chapter of Economy and Society. Both marginal utility theory and declining utility's roles in his writings were implied through his usage of instrumentally rational action that chapter.[228]

Economic calculation

Like his colleague Werner Sombart, Weber regarded economic calculation, and especially the double-entry bookkeeping method of business accounting, as one of the most important forms of the rationalisation that was associated with the development of modern capitalism.[229] Weber's preoccupation with the importance of economic calculation led him to critique socialism as a system that lacked a mechanism for allocating resources efficiently to satisfy human needs.[230] Otto Neurath, a socialist thinker, thought that prices would not exist and central planners would use in-kind, rather than monetary, economic calculation in a completely socialised economy.[231] According to Weber, this type of coordination would be inefficient, especially because it would be incapable of solving the problem of imputation, which related to the difficulties in accurately determining the relative values of capital goods.[232] Weber wrote that, under full socialism, the value of goods would have to be determined. However, there would be no clear method for doing so in that economic system. Planned economies were, therefore, irrational.[233] This argument against socialism was made independently, at about the same time, by Ludwig von Mises.[234] Weber himself had a significant influence on Mises, whom he had befriended when they were both at the University of Vienna in the spring of 1918. However, Mises ultimately regarded him as having been a historian, rather than an economist.[235]

Inspirations

Immanuel Kant and Karl Marx, two of Max Weber's influences

Max Weber was strongly influenced by German idealism, particularly by neo-Kantianism. He had been exposed to it by Heinrich Rickert, who was his professorial colleague at the University of Freiburg.[236] Especially important to Weber's work is the neo-Kantian belief that reality was essentially chaotic and incomprehensible, with all rational order deriving from the way the human mind focused attention on certain aspects of reality and organised the resulting perceptions.[237] Weber's opinions regarding the methodology of the social sciences showed parallels with the work of contemporary neo-Kantian philosopher and pioneering sociologist Georg Simmel.[238] Weber was also influenced by Kantian ethics more generally, which he nonetheless came to think of as obsolete in a modern age lacking in religious certainties.[239] His interpretation of Kant and neo-Kantianism was pessimistic as a result.[240]

Weber was responding to the effect that Friedrich Nietzsche's philosophy had on modern thought. His goal in the field of ethics was to find freedom that was not arbitrarily defined in what he interpreted as an age that moved past metaphysics. That represented a division between the parts of his thought that represented Kantianism and Nietzscheanism.[241] After his debate with Oswald Spengler in 1920, Weber was recorded as having said that the world was largely intellectually influenced by Nietzsche and Marx.[242] In The Protestant Work Ethic and the Spirit of Capitalism and "Science as a Vocation", Weber negatively described "die 'letzten Menschen'" ("the 'last men'"), who were Nietzschean "specialists without spirit" who Weber warned about in both texts.[243] Similarly, he also used Nietzsche's concept of ressentiment in his discussion of theodicy, but he interpreted it differently. Weber disliked Nietzsche's emotional approach to the subject and did not interpret it as having been a type of slave morality that was derived from Judaism.[244]

While a student in Charlottenburg, Weber read all forty volumes by Johann Wolfgang von Goethe, who later exerted an influence over his methodology and concepts.[8] For Weber, Goethe was one of the seminal figures in German history.[245] In his writings, including The Protestant Work Ethic and the Spirit of Capitalism, Weber quoted Goethe on several occasions.[9] His usage of "electoral affinity" in his writings may have been derived from Goethe, as it had been used as the title of one of Goethe's works.[246] Weber was also influenced by Goethe's usage of the Greek daimon ("fate"). That concept influenced Weber's perspective that one's fate was inevitable and that one was able to use experience to create intellectual passion.[247] He thought that Goethe, his Faust, and Nietzsche's Zarathustra were figures that represented the Übermensch and expressed the quality of human action by ceaselessly striving for knowledge.[248]

Another major influence in Weber's life was the writings of Karl Marx and the workings of socialist thought in academia and active politics.[249] While he shared some of Marx's consternation with bureaucratic systems and maligned them as having been capable of advancing their own logic to the detriment of human freedom and autonomy, Weber viewed conflict as perpetual and inevitable and did not host the spirit of a materially available utopia.[250] Writing in 1932, Karl Löwith contrasted the work of Marx and Weber, arguing that both were interested in the causes and effects of Western capitalism, but they viewed it through different lenses. Marx viewed capitalism through the lens of alienation, while Weber used the concept of rationalisation to interpret it.[251] Weber also expanded Marx's interpretation of alienation from the specific idea of the worker who was alienated from his work to similar situations that involved intellectuals and bureaucrats.[252] Scholars during the Cold War frequently interpreted Weber as having been "a bourgeois answer to Marx", but he was actually responding to the issues that were relevant to the bourgeoisie in Wilhelmine Germany. In that regard, he focused on the conflict between rationality and irrationality.[253]

Legacy

Weber's most influential work was on economic sociology, political sociology, and the sociology of religion. Along with Karl Marx and Émile Durkheim, he is commonly regarded as one of the founders of modern sociology.[254] He was instrumental in developing an antipositivist, hermeneutic, tradition in the social sciences.[255] Weber influenced many scholars across the political spectrum. Left-leaning social theorists, such as Theodor W. Adorno, Max Horkheimer, György Lukács and Jürgen Habermas were influenced by his discussion of modernity and its friction with modernization.[256] As part of that, his analysis of modernity and rationalisation significantly influenced the critical theory associated with the Frankfurt School.[257] Right-leaning scholars, including Carl Schmitt, Joseph Schumpeter, Leo Strauss, Hans Morgenthau, and Raymond Aron, emphasised different elements of his thought. They placed importance on his discussion of strong leaders in democracy, political ethic's relationship with value-freedom and value-relativism, and combatting bureaucracy through politically based struggle.[241] The scholars who have examined his works philosophically, including Strauss, Hans Henrik Bruun, and Alfred Schütz, have traditionally looked at them through the lens of Continental philosophy.[258]

Weber studies

Weberian scholarship's beginnings were delayed by the ongoing disruption of academic life in the Weimar Republic. Hyper-inflation caused Weber's support for parliamentary democracy to be countered by the decline the respect that professors had for it. The alienation that they experienced from politics caused many of them to become pessimistic and closer to the historical viewpoints espoused by Oswald Spengler in his The Decline of the West.[259] Furthermore, universities were coming under increased state control and influence. After the Nazi Party took power, that process accelerated. The previously dominant style of sociology, that of Alfred Vierkandt and Leopold von Wiese, was largely replaced by a sociology that was dominated by support for the Nazis. Hans Freyer and Othmar Spann were representative of that movement, while Werner Sombart moved towards support for collectivism. The rise of the Nazi Party had relegated Weber's scholarship to a marginal position in the Germany academy. However, some Weberian scholars had left Germany while this process was going on, with most of them settling in the United States and the United Kingdom.[260]

These scholars began to involve themselves in American and British scholarship at a time when Weber's writings, such as the General Economic History, were beginning to be translated into English. Talcott Parsons, an American scholar, was influenced by his readings of Weber and Sombart as a student in Germany during the 1920s. He obtained permission from Marianne Weber to publish a translation of The Protestant Work Ethic and the Spirit of Capitalism in his 1930 essay collection, the Collected Essays on the Sociology of Religion. This translated version, which was heavily edited by the publisher, was not initially successful.[261] Parsons had been using this translation as part of his effort to create an academic sociology, which resulted in his 1937 book the Structure of Social Action. In it, Parson's argued that Weber and Durkheim were foundational figures in sociology. His book was not successful until after the Second World War. He then published a translation of Economy and Society as The Theory of Social and Economic Organization. His increasing prominence as a scholar led to this volume's own elevated influence. Other translations began to appear, including C. Wright Mills and Hans Gerth's From Max Weber: Essays in Sociology in 1946. Their volume was a collection of excerpts from Weber's writings. In the last year of the decade, Edward Shils edited a translation of Weber's Collected Essays on Methodology, which was published as The Methodology of the Social Sciences.[262]

As the 1940s ended, Max Weber's reputation as a scholar had been rising through its interpretation through the lenses of Parsons's structural functionalism and Mills's conflict theory.[263] Over the course of the next few decades, continued publications of translated versions of Weber's works began to appear, including ones on law, religion, music, and the city. Despite the flawed nature of many of the translations, it became possible to obtain a largely complete view of Weber's scholarship. That was still impeded by the unorganised way in which the translations were published, which prevented scholars from knowing the connections between the different texts. In 1968, a complete translation of Economy and Society in the way that it was prepared by Marianne Weber was published.[264] While an interpretation of Weber that was separate from Parson's structural functionalism had begun with From Max Weber, a more political and historical interpretation was forwarded by Reinhard Bendix's 1948 Max Weber: An Intellectual Portrait, Ralf Dahrendorf's 1957 Class and Conflict in an Industrial Society, and John Rex's 1962 Key Problems in Sociological Theory. Raymond Aron's interpretation of Weber in his 1965 text, Main Currents in Sociological Thought, gave an alternative to Parson's perspective on the history of sociology. Weber, while still integral to it, was being framed as one of the three foundational figures, the other two were Karl Marx and Émile Durkheim. Anthony Giddens solidified that interpretation of the three scholars with the publication of his Capitalism and Modern Social Theory in 1971. After the end of the 1970s, more of Weber's less prominent publications began to be published. That effort coincided with the continued writings of critical commentaries on his works and idea, including the creation of a scholarly journal in 2000, Max Weber Studies, that is devoted to such scholarship.[265]

Max Weber-Gesamtausgabe

The idea of publishing a collected edition of Max Weber's complete works was pushed forward by Horst Baier in 1972. A year later, the Max Weber-Gesamtausgabe, a multi-volume set of all of Max Weber's writings, began to take shape.[266] Wolfgang J. Mommsen, Wolfgang Schluchter, Johannes Winckelmann, M. Rainer Lepsius, and Horst Baier were the initial editors. After Mommsen's death in 2004, Gangolf Hübinger succeeded him. Winckelmann, Lepsius, and Baier also died before the completion of the project.[267] The writings were organised in a combination of chronological order and by subject, with the material that was not intended to be published by Weber in purely chronological order. The final editions of each text were used, with the exception of The Protestant Ethic and the Spirit of Capitalism, which was published in both its first and final forms.[268] Mohr Siebeck was selected to publish the volumes.[269] The project was presented to the academic community in 1981 with the publication of a prospectus that was colloquially referred to as the "green brochure". It outlined the three sections of the series: "Writings and Speeches", "Letters", and "Lecture Manuscripts and Lecture Notes".[270] Four years later, the project entered publication.[271] It concluded in June 2020 and contains forty-seven volumes, including two index volumes.[272]

Bibliography

See also

Citations

  1. Kim 2022; Kaesler 1988, pp. 2–3; Radkau 2009, p. 5.
  2. Kaelber 2003, p. 38; Radkau 2009, p. 11.
  3. Kaelber 2003, p. 38; Radkau 2009, p. 5; Honigsheim 2017, p. 100.
  4. Kim 2022; Kaelber 2003, p. 38; Radkau 2009, p. 9.
  5. Kaelber 2003, p. 38; Ritzer 2009, p. 32; Honigsheim 2017, p. 100.
  6. Kaesler 1988, pp. 2–3, 14; Radkau 2009, pp. 91–92.
  7. Kaesler 1988, p. 2; Radkau 2009, p. 561.
  8. 1 2 Kaesler 1988, p. 2; McKinnon 2010, pp. 110–112; Kent 1983, pp. 297–303.
  9. 1 2 McKinnon 2010, pp. 110–112; Kent 1983, pp. 297–303.
  10. Kaesler 1988, pp. 2–3.
  11. Sica 2017, p. 24; Kaesler 2014, p. 180.
  12. Radkau 2009, pp. 31–33; Bendix & Roth 1977, pp. 1–2.
  13. Berman & Reid 2000, pp. 223–225; Allan 2005, p. 146; Honigsheim 2017, p. 101.
  14. Kaelber 2003, pp. 30–33.
  15. Kaelber 2003, p. 33; Honigsheim 2017, p. 239; Radkau 2009, p. 563.
  16. Bendix & Roth 1977, pp. 1–2; Kaelber 2003, p. 41; Radkau 2009, p. 563.
  17. Lachmann 2007, p. 143; Honigsheim 2017, p. 101.
  18. Kaelber 2003, p. 30; Radkau 2009, pp. 562–564.
  19. Mommsen & Steinberg 1984, pp. 2–9; Kaelber 2003, p. 36; Radkau 2009, p. 23.
  20. Allan 2005, p. 146; Radkau 2009, pp. 31–33.
  21. Kaesler 2014, pp. 191, 207; Gordon 2020.
  22. Kaelber 2003, p. 39; Ritzer 2009, p. 32; Gordon 2020.
  23. Radkau 2009, pp. 39–40, 562; Kaelber 2003, pp. 36–38.
  24. Radkau 2009, p. 564.
  25. Kaelber 2003, pp. 39–40.
  26. Allan 2005, p. 146; Frommer & Frommer 1993, p. 165.
  27. Kim 2022; Lengermann & Niebrugge-Brantley 1998, p. 193; Frommer & Frommer 1993, p. 165.
  28. Hanke 2009, pp. 351–357; Honigsheim 2017, p. 239.
  29. Radkau 2009, pp. 343–344, 360; Lepsius 2004, pp. 11–14.
  30. Demm 2017, pp. 64, 82–83; Lepsius 2004, pp. 11–14.
  31. Poggi 2006, p. 5; Mommsen 1992, p. 19; Radkau 2009, p. 563.
  32. Kim 2022; Radkau 2009, pp. 79–82.
  33. Kim 2022; Poggi 2006, p. 5; Radkau 2009, pp. 79–82.
  34. Mommsen & Steinberg 1984, pp. 54–56; Hobsbawm 1987, p. 152; Radkau 2009, pp. 564–565.
  35. Bendix & Roth 1977, pp. 1–2; Lachmann 2007, p. 143; Honigsheim 2017, p. 239.
  36. Radkau 2009, pp. 125–128; Craig 1988.
  37. Kaesler 2014, pp. 429–431; Radkau 2009, pp. 134–135; Mommsen & Steinberg 1984, pp. 123–126.
  38. Kaesler 2014, pp. 436–441; Radkau 2009, pp. 134–135, 330; Mommsen & Steinberg 1984, pp. 126–130.
  39. Radkau 2009, p. 564; Bendix & Roth 1977, pp. 1–2; Lachmann 2007, p. 143.
  40. Kim 2022; Honigsheim 2017, pp. ix–x.
  41. Radkau 2009, pp. 65–66; Kim 2022; Weber 1999, p. 7.
  42. Radkau 2009, pp. 65–69; Bendix & Roth 1977, pp. 1–2; Frommer & Frommer 1993, pp. 163–164.
  43. Radkau 2009, p. 143; Bendix & Roth 1977, pp. 2–3.
  44. Radkau 2009, p. 143.
  45. Weber 1964, pp. 641–642; Radkau 2009, pp. 170–171.
  46. Kim 2022; Roth 1976, pp. 306–318; Bendix & Roth 1977, p. 3.
  47. 1 2 3 Bendix & Roth 1977, pp. 49–50; Weber 1999, p. 8.
  48. Weber 2013, pp. xi–xii; Kim 2022.
  49. Weber 2013, pp. xviii, xxxii–xxxiii.
  50. Weber 2013, p. xviii; Radkau 2009, pp. 195–197.
  51. 1 2 Radkau 2009, pp. 191–192.
  52. Radkau 2009, pp. 191–192; Weber 2013, pp. xxxii–xxxiii.
  53. 1 2 Radkau 2009, pp. 186–190; Weber 2013, p. 245; Baehr 2001, pp. 153–154.
  54. Radkau 2009, pp. 191–192; Weber 2013, pp. xlvii–l; Kim 2022.
  55. Roth 2005, pp. 82–83; Scaff 2011, pp. 11–24; Smith 2019, p. 96.
  56. Scaff 2011, pp. 11–24; Radkau 2009, pp. 296–299; Honigsheim 2017, pp. 24–25.
  57. Scaff 2011, pp. 117–119; Smith 2019, pp. 96–97; Honigsheim 2017, pp. 24–25.
  58. Roth 2005, pp. 82–83; Scaff 2011, pp. 11–24; Smith 2019, pp. 97–100.
  59. Lachmann 2007, p. 143; Bendix & Roth 1977, p. 3.
  60. Kim 2022; Radkau 2009, p. 277.
  61. Whimster 2016, p. 8; Radkau 2009, pp. 358, 280; Löwy & Varikas 2022, p. 94.
  62. Whimster 2016, pp. 18–20; Radkau 2009, pp. 383–385; Löwy & Varikas 2022, p. 100.
  63. Whimster 2016, p. 8; Radkau 2009, pp. 358, 280–283; Löwy & Varikas 2022, p. 94.
  64. Whimster 2016, pp. 8–9; Radkau 2009, pp. 358, 280–283; Löwy & Varikas 2022, p. 100.
  65. Bendix & Roth 1977, p. 3; Kaesler 1988, p. 18; Radkau 2009, pp. 454–456.
  66. Mommsen & Steinberg 1984, pp. 196–198; Kaesler 1988, pp. 18–19; Weber & Turner 2014, pp. 22–23.
  67. Kim 2022; Bruhns 2018, pp. 37–40; Craig 1988.
  68. Kim 2022; Bruhns 2018, pp. 40, 43–44; Craig 1988.
  69. Radkau 2009, pp. 483–487; Levy 2016, pp. 87–89; Kaesler 2014, pp. 747–748.
  70. Radkau 2009, pp. 484–486; Levy 2016, pp. 88–90; Kaesler 2014, pp. 747–748.
  71. Radkau 2009, pp. 486–487; Levy 2016, pp. 90–91; Kaesler 2014, pp. 747–748.
  72. Radkau 2009, pp. 485–487; Levy 2016, pp. 89–91; Kaesler 2014, pp. 749–751.
  73. Radkau 2009, pp. 487–491; Weber 2004, p. xix; Gane 2002, p. 53.
  74. Radkau 2009, pp. 487–491; Weber 2004, pp. xxv–xxvi; Tribe 2018, pp. 130–133.
  75. Weber 2004, pp. xxx–xxxii; Gane 2002, pp. 45–49; Tribe 2018, pp. 131–132.
  76. Mommsen & Steinberg 1984, pp. 303–308; Radkau 2009, pp. 513–514; Kim 2022.
  77. Kaesler 2014, pp. 866–870; Bendix & Roth 1977, p. 3; Radkau 2009, pp. 511–512.
  78. Radkau 2009, pp. 507–508.
  79. Mommsen & Steinberg 1984, pp. 301–302; Kaesler 1988, p. 22.
  80. Waters & Waters 2015a, p. 20; Radkau 2009, pp. 500–503.
  81. Waters & Waters 2015a, p. 20; Honigsheim 2017, p. 246.
  82. Kim 2022; Kaesler 2014, pp. 868–869; Honigsheim 2017, p. 246.
  83. Waters & Waters 2015a, pp. 21, 196; Radkau 2009, p. 514; Weber 2004, pp. xxxiv–xxxv.
  84. Waters & Waters 2015a, pp. 21, 196; Radkau 2009, p. 516.
  85. Radkau 2009, pp. 514–518; Weber 2004, pp. xxxiv–xxxviii; Gane 2002, pp. 64–65.
  86. Weber 2004, pp. l–li; Bendix & Roth 1977, pp. 294–295; Macionis 2012, p. 88.
  87. Radkau 2009, pp. 514–518; Weber 2004, pp. xxxiv–xxxviii.
  88. Radkau 2009, pp. 542–543; Kaesler 2014, p. 883.
  89. Radkau 2009, p. 543; Kaesler 2014, pp. 884–887.
  90. Kim 2022; Lachmann 2007, p. 144; Bendix & Roth 1977, p. 3.
  91. Kim 2022; Weber & Cohen 2017, p. lxxxiii.
  92. Radkau 2009, pp. 491–492; Kaesler 2014, pp. 761–764.
  93. Radkau 2009, pp. 529, 570; Kaesler 2014, pp. 839–841.
  94. Mommsen & Steinberg 1984, pp. 327–328.
  95. Kaesler 2014, pp. 906–907; Spengler & Hughes 1991, pp. xv–xvi.
  96. 1 2 Kaesler 2014, pp. 906–907; Farrenkopf 1992, p. 1; Spengler & Hughes 1991, pp. xv–xvi.
  97. Kaesler 2014, pp. 906–907; Spengler & Hughes 1991, pp. xv–xvi; Weber 1964, pp. 554–555.
  98. Radkau 2009, pp. 539, 541–542; Kaesler 2014, pp. 921–922.
  99. Radkau 2009, pp. 542, 547–548; Kaesler 2014, pp. 921–923.
  100. Radkau 2009, pp. 545–446; Hanke 2009, pp. 349–350; Honigsheim 2017, p. 239.
  101. Kim 2022; Radkau 2009, pp. 545–546; Hanke 2009, pp. 349–350.
  102. Radkau 2009, pp. 549–550; Hanke 2009, pp. 349–350; Kaesler 2014, pp. 16–19.
  103. Roth 2016, pp. 250–253; Whimster 2023, p. 82; Hanke 2009, pp. 349–350.
  104. Denhardt 2010, p. 27.
  105. 1 2 Sibeon 2004, pp. 37–38.
  106. Sibeon 2004, pp. 37–38; Allan 2005, pp. 144–148.
  107. Kim 2022; Ritzer 2009, p. 31; Weber 2011, pp. 7–32.
  108. Kim 2022; Heath 2020; Swedberg & Agevall 2016, pp. 256–257.
  109. Kim 2022; Swedberg & Agevall 2016, pp. 256–257.
  110. Kim 2022; Swedberg & Agevall 2016, pp. 228–230.
  111. Weber 1994, p. 321.
  112. Heath 2020; Ritzer 2009, p. 31.
  113. 1 2 Heath 2020.
  114. Weber 1978a, p. xxxiii; Allan 2005, p. 149; Kim 2022.
  115. Kaesler 1988, p. 187; Beiser 2011, pp. 551–552.
  116. Kim 2022; Swedberg & Agevall 2016, pp. 15–16; Beiser 2011, pp. 525–528.
  117. Beiser 2011, pp. 527–529, 546.
  118. Allan 2005, p. 153.
  119. 1 2 Allan 2005, p. 148.
  120. Kaesler 1988, pp. 184–187; Swedberg & Agevall 2016, p. 365; Beiser 2011, pp. 551–552.
  121. Kaesler 1988, pp. 185–189; Swedberg & Agevall 2016, p. 365; Beiser 2011, pp. 551–552.
  122. Kaesler 1988, pp. 184–187; Swedberg & Agevall 2016, pp. 364–365; Beiser 2011, pp. 551–553.
  123. Kim 2022; Ritzer 2009, p. 30; Allan 2005, p. 151.
  124. Allan 2005, p. 151.
  125. Bendix & Roth 1977, pp. 57–61; Allan 2005, p. 162.
  126. 1 2 3 Allan 2005, p. 162.
  127. Weigert 1991, p. 110.
  128. 1 2 Habermas 1990, pp. 1–2.
  129. Kim 2022; Weber 2004, pp. l–li.
  130. Kim 2022; Macionis 2012, p. 88.
  131. Kim 2022; Radkau 2009, pp. 187–189.
  132. Kim 2022; Habermas 1990, pp. 1–2.
  133. Kim 2022; Gane 2002, pp. 24–26.
  134. Kim 2022; Ritzer 2009, pp. 38–42; Allan 2005, p. 177.
  135. Kim 2022; Gane 2002, pp. 16–23.
  136. Josephson Storm 2017, pp. 299–300.
  137. Allan 2005, pp. 151–152.
  138. Boehmer 2001, pp. 277–278; Kaesler 2014, p. 70; Radkau 2009, pp. 367–368.
  139. Radkau 2009, pp. 367–368; Kaesler 2014, pp. 702–703.
  140. Kaesler 2014, pp. 703–704; Boehmer 2001, pp. 277–278.
  141. Radkau 2009, pp. 370–371.
  142. Schluchter 2018, pp. 87–89; Bellah 1999, p. 280.
  143. Bendix & Roth 1977, p. 285; Bellah 1999, p. 280.
  144. Bendix & Roth 1977, p. 285.
  145. Bendix & Roth 1977, p. 285; Kim 2022.
  146. Allan 2005, pp. 154–155.
  147. Allan 2005, p. 158.
  148. Weber 1999, p. 22–23; Bendix & Roth 1977, pp. 49–50.
  149. Ritzer 2009, pp. 35–37; Bendix & Roth 1977, pp. 57–59.
  150. Radkau 2009, pp. 96, 193; Bendix & Roth 1977, pp. 63–64.
  151. Weber 2013, pp. 15–16.
  152. Ritzer 2009, pp. 35–37.
  153. Bendix & Roth 1977, p. 57.
  154. Bendix & Roth 1977, pp. 60–61; Weber 2013, p. xxx.
  155. Bendix & Roth 1977, pp. 55–58; Weber 2013, p. xxviii.
  156. Ritzer 2009, pp. 35–37; Bendix & Roth 1977, pp. 55–58.
  157. Ritzer 2009, pp. 35–37; Bendix & Roth 1977, pp. 60–63.
  158. Swedberg & Agevall 2016, pp. 10–12.
  159. Weber 2013, pp. xviii, xxxii–xxxiii; Allan 2005, pp. 162–163; Bendix & Roth 1977, pp. 58–61.
  160. Weber 1968, pp. ix–xi.
  161. Bendix & Roth 1977, pp. 114–116; Radkau 2009, pp. 477–478; Whimster 2007, pp. 134–135, 212.
  162. Bendix & Roth 1977, pp. 98–99; Schluchter 2014, pp. 12–13.
  163. Bendix & Roth 1977, pp. 135–141; Whimster 2007, pp. 134–135; Schluchter 2014, p. 19.
  164. Bendix & Roth 1977, pp. 135–141; Schluchter 2014, p. 19.
  165. Ritzer 2009, pp. 37–38; Bendix & Roth 1977, pp. 135–141.
  166. Bendix & Roth 1977, pp. 135–141; Schluchter 2014, p. 19; Whimster 2007, p. 188.
  167. Bendix & Roth 1977, pp. 135–141; Schluchter 2014, pp. 23–25.
  168. Bendix & Roth 1977, pp. 142–158; Schluchter 2018, pp. 98–99.
  169. Ritzer 2009, pp. 37–38; Thapar 2018, pp. 123–125.
  170. Kalberg 2017, pp. 238–240.
  171. Ritzer 2009, p. 35; Gellner 1982, pp. 535–537; Kalberg 2017, p. 240.
  172. Ritzer 2009, p. 35; Weber & Turner 2014, p. 396; Kalberg 2017, p. 240.
  173. Bendix & Roth 1977, pp. 198–199; Schluchter 2018, pp. 101–102.
  174. Bendix & Roth 1977, pp. 198–199; Schluchter 2018, pp. 92–93.
  175. Bendix & Roth 1977, pp. 198–199.
  176. Bendix & Roth 1977, pp. 90, 198–199; Schluchter 2018, p. 98.
  177. Bendix & Roth 1977, pp. 198–199; Schluchter 2018, pp. 96–97; Kalberg 2017, p. 237.
  178. 1 2 Bendix & Roth 1977, pp. 200–201.
  179. Bendix & Roth 1977, pp. 200–201; Kaesler 1988, p. 127.
  180. Bendix & Roth 1977, pp. 204–205.
  181. Kaesler 1988, p. 127; Bendix & Roth 1977, pp. 200–201; Radkau 2009, pp. 444–446.
  182. Kaesler 1988, pp. 127–130.
  183. Adair-Toteff 2013, pp. 87–90; Swedberg & Agevall 2016, pp. 348–349; Christiano, Swatos & Kivisto 2008, pp. 6–7.
  184. Adair-Toteff 2013, pp. 88–89; Turner 1996, p. 149.
  185. Adair-Toteff 2013, pp. 99–102; Turner 1996, p. 158.
  186. Adair-Toteff 2013, pp. 94–97; Turner 1996, pp. 147–148.
  187. Swedberg & Agevall 2016, pp. 348–349; Christiano, Swatos & Kivisto 2008, pp. 142–143; Plye & Davidson 1998, pp. 498–499.
  188. Christiano, Swatos & Kivisto 2008, pp. 142–143.
  189. Plye & Davidson 1998, pp. 498–499; Swedberg & Agevall 2016, pp. 348–349.
  190. Weber 2004, p. 34; Warner 1991, pp. 9–10; Palonen 2011, pp. 104–105.
  191. Warner 1991, pp. 9–10.
  192. Weber 2004, p. xli; Marlin 2002, pp. 155; Radkau 2009, pp. 515–516.
  193. Radkau 2009, pp. 515–516; Marlin 2002, pp. 155–156.
  194. Weber 2004, p. 34; Bendix & Roth 1977, pp. 294–296; Macionis 2012, p. 88.
  195. Bendix & Roth 1977, p. 296.
  196. Ritzer 2009, pp. 37–41.
  197. Bendix & Roth 1977, pp. 303–305.
  198. Ritzer 2009, pp. 38–42.
  199. 1 2 Ritzer 2009, pp. 38–42; Swedberg & Agevall 2016, pp. 18–21.
  200. Sashkin & Sashkin 2003, p. 52.
  201. Hooghe 2001, p. 40.
  202. 1 2 Allan 2005, pp. 172–176.
  203. Swedberg & Agevall 2016, pp. 18–21; Allan 2005, pp. 172–176.
  204. Swedberg & Agevall 2016, pp. 18–21; Ritzer 2005, p. 55.
  205. Swedberg & Agevall 2016, pp. 18–21.
  206. Bendix & Roth 1977, pp. 85–87.
  207. 1 2 Weber 2015b, pp. 37–58.
  208. Waters & Waters 2016, pp. 1–2.
  209. Swedberg & Agevall 2016, pp. 41–42, 192; Waters & Waters 2016, pp. 2–3.
  210. Bendix & Roth 1977, pp. 79.
  211. Zubaida 2005–2006, p. 112; Kaesler 1988, pp. 42–43; Bendix & Roth 1977, pp. 70–73.
  212. Bendix & Roth 1977, pp. 79; Zubaida 2005–2006, pp. 112–113.
  213. Swedberg & Agevall 2016, p. 283.
  214. Swedberg & Agevall 2016, pp. 88–89; Kaesler 1988, pp. 44–46.
  215. Petersen 2017, p. 29; Baehr 2002, pp. 22–23.
  216. Swedberg 1999, pp. 561–582.
  217. Beiser 2011, pp. 525–527; Maclachlan 2017, pp. 1161–1163; Radkau 2009, p. 138.
  218. Swedberg & Agevall 2016, p. 103.
  219. Whimster 2023, p. 82; Roth 2016, pp. 250–253; Hanke 2009, pp. 349–350.
  220. Roth 2016, pp. 250–253; Whimster 2023, p. 82.
  221. Roth 2016, pp. 250–253.
  222. Maclachlan 2017, pp. 1163–1164; Callison 2022, p. 276.
  223. Swedberg & Agevall 2016, pp. 211–212; Heath 2020.
  224. Heath 2020; Swedberg & Agevall 2016, p. 211.
  225. Radkau 2009, p. 138; Schweitzer 1975, pp. 279–292; Swedberg 1999, pp. 564–568.
  226. Parsons 2007, pp. 236–237; Honigsheim 2017, pp. 187–188.
  227. Mass 2009, pp. 507–511; Swedberg 1999, p. 564; Stigler 1950, p. 377.
  228. Parsons 2007, pp. 235–238.
  229. Swedberg & Agevall 2016, pp. 22–23.
  230. Tribe 2009, pp. 157–158.
  231. Tribe 2009, pp. 143–147; Cat 2023.
  232. Tribe 2009, p. 158–159; Cat 2023.
  233. Hülsmann 2007, pp. 392–396.
  234. Tribe 2009, p. 142; Hülsmann 2007, pp. 392–396.
  235. Mises & Hayek 2009, pp. xvi–xvii; Maclachlan 2017, p. 1166; Kolev 2020, p. 44.
  236. Kim 2022; Barker 1980, pp. 224–225; Eliaeson 1990, pp. 17–18.
  237. Kim 2022; Barker 1980, pp. 241–242.
  238. Frisby 2002, p. 46.
  239. Kim 2022; Turner 2011, pp. 85–86; Albrow 1990, pp. 47–50.
  240. Kim 2022; Barker 1980, pp. 224–225.
  241. 1 2 Kim 2022.
  242. Weber 1964, pp. 554–555; Turner 2011, p. 77; Radkau 2009, p. 167.
  243. Turner 2011, p. 77; Kent 1983, pp. 301–302; Tribe 2018, p. 134.
  244. Adair-Toteff 2013, pp. 99–102.
  245. Kent 1983, pp. 301–304; McKinnon 2010, pp. 110–112.
  246. McKinnon 2010, pp. 110–111; Kent 1983, p. 308.
  247. Scaff 1989, pp. 68; Albrow 1990, p. 70; Sahni 2001, p. 424.
  248. Kent 1983, pp. 301–304; Sahni 2001, pp. 423–424.
  249. Weber 1994, p. 288; Turner 2011, p. 77; Radkau 2009, p. 167.
  250. Weber 1994, p. 288; Mayer 1975, pp. 710–711.
  251. Löwith & Turner 1993, p. 34.
  252. Albrow 1990, p. 108.
  253. Albrow 1990, pp. 106–109; Honigsheim 2017, pp. 187–188; Löwith & Turner 1993, pp. 34–35, 62.
  254. Petersen 2017, p. 29; Scott 2019, pp. 183–184.
  255. Rhoads 2010, p. 40.
  256. Kim 2022; Löwy 1996, pp. 431–446.
  257. Löwy 1996, pp. 431–446.
  258. Turner 2007, p. 39.
  259. Scott 2019, p. 179.
  260. Scott 2019, pp. 179–180.
  261. Scott 2019, p. 180.
  262. Scott 2019, pp. 180–182; Fish 2017, pp. 125–127; Oakes & Vidich 1999, pp. 404–405.
  263. Scott 2019, pp. 182–183; Fish 2017, pp. 125–127.
  264. Scott 2019, pp. 182–183.
  265. Scott 2019, pp. 183–184; Smith 2019, p. 101.
  266. Hanke, Hübinger & Schwentker 2012, pp. 65–70.
  267. Lichtblau 2022, pp. 74–76.
  268. Lichtblau 2022, pp. 79–81.
  269. Hanke, Hübinger & Schwentker 2012, pp. 77–79; Lichtblau 2022, pp. 74, 79; Adair-Toteff 2014, p. 117.
  270. Hanke, Hübinger & Schwentker 2012, p. 84.
  271. Hanke, Hübinger & Schwentker 2012, pp. 90–91; Lichtblau 2022, pp. 74–75; Adair-Toteff 2014, p. 113.
  272. Lichtblau 2022, pp. 74–75.

General and cited sources

Further reading

Online editions

This article is issued from Wikipedia. The text is licensed under Creative Commons - Attribution - Sharealike. Additional terms may apply for the media files.