In economics, dichotomous preferences (DP) are preference relations that divide the set of alternatives to two subsets: "Good" versus "Bad".
From ordinal utility perspective, DP means that for every two alternatives :[1]: 292
From cardinal utility perspective, DP means that for each agent, there are two utility levels: low and high, and for every alternative :
A common way to let people express dichotomous preferences is using approval ballots, in which each voter can either "approve" or "reject" each alternative.
In fair item assignment
In the context of fair item assignment, DP can be represented by a mathematical logic formula:[1]: 292 for every agent, there is a formula that describes his desired bundles. An agent is satisfied if-and-only-if he receives a bundle that satisfies the formula.
A special case of DP is single-mindedness. A single-minded agent wants a very specific bundle; he is happy if-and-only-if he receives this bundle, or any bundle that contains it. Such preferences appear in real-life, for example, in the problem of allocating classrooms to schools: each school i needs a number di of classes; the school has utility 1 if it gets all di classes in the same place and 0 otherwise. [2][3][4]
Collective choice under DP
Without money
Suppose a mechanism selects a lottery over outcomes. The utility of each agent, under this mechanism, is the probability that one of his Good outcomes is selected.
The utilitarian mechanism averages over outcomes with largest “approval”. It is Pareto efficient, strategyproof, anonymous and neutral.
It is impossible to attain these properties in addition to proportionality - giving each agent a utility of at least 1/n; or at least the fraction of good to feasible outcomes. [5] conjecture that no ex ante efficient and strategyproof mechanism guarantees a strictly positive utility to all agents, and prove a weaker statement.
With money
Suppose all agents have DP cardinal utility, where each agent is characterized by a single number - (so that ).
[6] identify a new condition, generation monotonicity, that is necessary and sufficient for implementation by a truthful mechanisms in any dichotomous domain (see Monotonicity (mechanism design)).
If such a domain satisfies a richness condition, then a weaker version of generation monotonicity, 2-generation monotonicity (equivalent to 3-cycle monotonicity), is necessary and sufficient for implementation.
This result can be used to derive the optimal mechanism in a one-sided matching problem with agents who have dichotomous types
References
- 1 2 Brandt, Felix; Conitzer, Vincent; Endriss, Ulle; Lang, Jérôme; Procaccia, Ariel D. (2016). Handbook of Computational Social Choice. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 9781107060432. (free online version)
- ↑ Bogomolnaia, Anna; Moulin, Herve (2004). "Random Matching Under Dichotomous Preferences". Econometrica. 72 (1): 257–279. doi:10.1111/j.1468-0262.2004.00483.x. ISSN 1468-0262.
- ↑ Kurokawa, David; Procaccia, Ariel D.; Shah, Nisarg (2015-06-15). "Leximin Allocations in the Real World". Proceedings of the Sixteenth ACM Conference on Economics and Computation. ACM. pp. 345–362. doi:10.1145/2764468.2764490. ISBN 9781450334105. S2CID 1060279.
- ↑ Ortega, Josué (2020-01-01). "Multi-unit assignment under dichotomous preferences". Mathematical Social Sciences. 103: 15–24. arXiv:1703.10897. doi:10.1016/j.mathsocsci.2019.11.003. ISSN 0165-4896.
- ↑ Bogomolnaia, Anna; Moulin, Hervé; Stong, Richard (2005). "Collective choice under dichotomous preferences". Journal of Economic Theory. 122 (2): 165. CiteSeerX 10.1.1.134.211. doi:10.1016/j.jet.2004.05.005.
- ↑ Mishra, Debasis; Roy, Souvik (2013). "Implementation in multidimensional dichotomous domains". Theoretical Economics. 8 (2): 431. doi:10.3982/TE1239. hdl:10419/150197.